by Pierre-Joseph Proudhon
Translated from the Voix du Peuple
of December 3, 1849,
by Benj. R. Tucker.
The Revolution of February raised two leading questions: one
economic, the question of labor and property; the other political, the question
of government or the State.
On the first of these questions the socialistic democracy is
substantially in accord. They admit that it is not a question of the seizure
and division of property, or even of its repurchase. Neither is it a question
of dishonorably levying additional taxes on the wealthy and property-holding
classes, which, while violating the principle of property recognized in the
constitution, would serve only to overturn the general economy and aggravate
the situation of the proletariat. The economic reform consists, on the one
hand, in opening usurious credit to competition and thereby causing capital to
lose its income,—in other words, in identifying, in every citizen to the same
degree, the capacity of the laborer and that of the capitalist; on the other
hand, in abolishing the whole system of existing taxes, which fall only on the
laborer and the poor man, and replacing them all by a single tax on capital, as
an insurance premium.
By these two great reforms social economy is reconstructed
from top to bottom, commercial and industrial relations are inverted, and the
profits, now assured to the capitalist, return to the laborer. Competition, now
anarchical and subversive, becomes emulative and fruitful; markets no longer
being wanting, the workingman and employer, intimately connected, have nothing
more to fear from stagnation or suspension. A new order is established upon the
old institutions abolished or regenerated.
On this point the revolutionary course is laid out; the
meaning of the movement is known. Whatever modification may appear in practice,
the reform will be effected according to these principles and on these bases;
the Revolution has no other issue. The economic problem, then, may be
considered solved.
It is far from being the same with the political
problem,—that is, with the disposal to be made in the future, of government and
the State. On this point the question is not even stated; it has not been
recognized by the public conscience and the intelligence of the masses. The
economic Revolution being accomplished, as we have just seen, can government,
the State, continue to exist? Ought it to continue to exist? This no one,
either in democracy or out of it, dares to call in question; and yet it is the
problem which, if we would escape new catastrophes, must next be solved.
We affirm, then, and as yet we are alone in affirming, that
with the economic Revolution, no longer in dispute, the State must entirely
disappear; that this disappearance of the State is the necessary consequence of
the organization of credit and the reform of taxation; that, as an effect of
this double innovation government becomes first useless and then impossible;
that in this respect it is in the same category with feudal property, lending
at interest, absolute and constitutional monarchy, judicial institutions, etc.,
all of which have served in the education of liberty, but which fall and vanish
when liberty has arrived at its fullness. Others, on the contrary, in the front
ranks of whom we distinguish Louis Blanc and Pierre Leroux, maintain that,
after the economic revolution, it is necessary to continue the State, but in an
organized form, furnishing however, as yet no principle or plan for its
organization. For them the political question, instead of being annihilated by
identification with the economic question always subsists, they favor an
extension of the prerogatives of the State, of power, of authority, of
government. They change names only; for example, instead of master-State they
say servant-State, as if a change of words sufficed to transform things! Above
this system of government, about which nothing is known, hovers a system of
religion whose dogma is equally unknown, whose ritual is unknown, whose object,
on earth and in heaven, is unknown.
This, then is the question which at present divides the
socialistic democracy, now in accord, or nearly so, on other matters: Must the
State continue to exist after the question of labor and capital shall be
practically solved? In other words, shall we always have, as we have had
hitherto, a political constitution apart from the social constitution?
We reply in the negative. We maintain that, capital and
labor once identified, society exists by itself, and has no further need of
government. We are, therefore, as we have more than once announced, anarchists.
Anarchy is the condition of existence of adult society, as hierarchy is the
condition of primitive society. There is a continual progress in human society
from hierarchy to anarchy.
Louis Blanc and Pierre Leroux affirm the contrary. In
addition to their capacity of socialists they retain that of politicians; they
are men of government and authority, statesmen.
To settle the difference, we have, then, to consider the
State, no longer from the point of view of the old society, which naturally and
necessarily produced it, and which approaches its end, but from the point of
view of the new society, which is, or must be, the result of the two
fundamental and correlative reforms of credit and taxation.
Now if we prove that, from this last point of view, the
State, considered in its nature rests on a thoroughly false hypothesis; that,
in the second place, considered in its object, the State finds no excuse for
its existence save in a second hypothesis, equally false; that, finally,
considered in the reasons for its continuance, the State again can appeal only
to an hypothesis as false as the two others,—these three points cleared up, the
question will be settled, the State will be regarded as a superfluous, and
consequently harmful and impossible, thing; government will be a contradiction.
Let us proceed at once with the analysis:—
I. Of the nature of the State.
“What is the State?” asks Louis Blanc.
And he replies:—
“The State, under monarchical rule, is the power of one man,
the tyranny of a single individual.
“The State, under oligarchical rule, is the power of a small
number of men, the tyranny of a few.
“The State, under aristocratic rule, is the power of a
class, the tyranny of many.
“The State, under anarchical rule is the power of the first
comer who happens to be the most intelligent and the strongest; it is the
tyranny of chaos.
“The State, under democratic rule, is the power of all the
people, served by their elect, it is the reign of liberty.”
Of the twenty-five or thirty thousand readers of Louis
Blanc, perhaps there are not ten to whom this definition of the State did not
seem conclusive, and who do not repeat, after the master: The State is the
power of one, of a few, of many, of all, or of the first comer, according as
the word State is prefaced by one of these other adjectives,—monarchical,
oligarchical, aristocratic, democratic, or anarchical. The delegates of the
Luxembourg—who think themselves robbed, it seems, when any one allows himself
to hold an opinion different from theirs on the meaning and tendencies of the
Revolution of February—in a letter that has been made public, have done me the
honor to inform me that they regard Louis Blanc’s answer as quite triumphant,
and that I can say nothing in reply. It would seem that none of the
citizen-delegates ever have studied Greek. Otherwise, they would have seen that
their master and friend, Louis Blanc, instead of defining the State, has only
translated into French the Greek words monos, one; aligoï, a few; aristoï, the
great; démos, the people; and the privative a, which means no. It is by the use
of these qualifying terms that Aristotle has distinguished the various forms of
the State, which is designated by the word archê, authority, government, State.
We ask pardon of our readers, but it is not our fault if the political science
of the Luxembourg does not go beyond etymology.
And mark the artifice! Louis Blanc, in his translation, only
had to use the word tyranny four times, tyranny of one, tyranny of many, etc.,
and to avoid it once, power of the people, served by their elect, to win
applause.
Every state save the democratic, according to Louis Blanc, is
tyranny. Anarchy especially receives a peculiar treatment; it is the power of
the first comer who happens to be the most intelligent and the strongest; it is
the tyranny of chaos. What a monster must be this first comer, who, first comer
that he is, nevertheless happens to be the most intelligent and the strongest,
and who exercises his tyranny in chaos! After that who could prefer anarchy to
this charming government of all the people, served so well, as we know, by
their elect?
How overwhelming it is, to be sure! at the first blow we find
ourselves flat on the ground. O rhetorician!
thank God for having created for
your express benefit, in the nineteenth century, such stupidity as that of your
so-called delegates of the working classes; otherwise you would have perished
under a storm of hisses the first time you touched a pen.
What is the State? This question must be answered. The list
of the various forms of the State, which Louis Blanc, after Aristotle, has
prepared, has taught us nothing. As for Pierre Leroux, it is not worth while to
interrogate him; he would tell us that the question is inconsiderate; that the
State has always existed; that it always will exist,—the final reason of
conservatives and old women.
The State is the EXTERNAL constitution of the social power.
By this external constitution of its power and sovereignty,
the people does not govern itself; now one individual, now several, by a title
either elective or hereditary, are charged with governing it, with managing it
affairs, with negotiating and compromising in its name; in a word, with
performing all the acts of a father of a family, a guardian, a manager, or a
proxy, furnished with a general, absolute, and irrevocable power of attorney.
This external constitution of the collective power, to which
the Greeks gave the name archê, sovereignty, authority, government, rests then
on this hypothesis: that a people, that the collective being which we call
society, cannot govern itself, think, act, express itself, unaided, like beings
endowed with individual personality; that, to do these things, it must be
represented by one or more individuals, who, by any title whatever, are
regarded as custodians of the will of the people, and its agents. According to
this hypothesis, it is impossible for the collective power, which belongs
essentially to the mass, to express itself and act directly, without the
mediation of organs expressly established and, so to speak, posted ad hoc. It
seems, we say,—and this is the explanation of the constitution of the State in
all its varieties and forms,—that the collective being, society, existing only
in the mind, cannot make itself felt save through monarchical incarnation,
aristocratic usurpation, or democratic mandate; consequently, that all special
and personal manifestation is forbidden it.
Now it is precisely this conception of the collective being,
of it life, its action, its unity, its individuality, its personality,—for
society is a person, understand! just as entire humanity is a person,—it is
this conception of the collective human being that we deny today; and it is for
that reason that we deny the State also, that we deny government, that we
exclude from society, when economically revolutionized, every constitution of
the popular power, either without or within the mass, by hereditary royalty,
feudal institution, or democratic delegation.
We affirm, on the contrary, that the people, that society,
that the mass, can and ought to govern itself by itself; to thing, act, rise,
and halt, like a man; to manifest itself, in fine, in its physical,
intellectual, and moral individuality, without the aid of all these spokesmen,
who formerly were despots, who now are aristocrats, who from time to time have
been pretended delegates, fawners on or servants of the crowd, and whom we call
plainly and simply popular agitators, demagogues.
In short:
We deny government and the State, because we affirm that
which the founders of States have never believed in, the personality and
autonomy of the masses.
We affirm further that every constitution of the State has
no other object than to lead society to this condition of autonomy; that the
different forms of the State, from absolute monarchy to representative
democracy, are all only middle terms, illogical and unstable positions, serving
one after another as transitions or steps to liberty, and forming the rounds of
the political ladder upon which societies mount to self-consciousness and
self-possession.
We affirm, finally, that this anarchy, which expresses, as
we now see, the highest degree of liberty and order at which humanity can
arrive, is the true formula of the Republic, the goal towards with the
Revolution or February urges us; so that between the Republic and the
government, between universal suffrage and the State, there is a contradiction.
These systematic affirmations we establish in two ways:
first, by the historical and negative method, demonstrating that no
establishment of authority, no organization of the collective force from without,
is henceforth possible for us. This demonstration we commenced in the
“Confessions of a Revolutionist,” in reciting the fall of all the governments
which have succeeded one another in France for sixty years, discovering the
cause of their abolition, and in the last place signalizing the exhaustion and
death of authority in the corrupted reign of Louis Philippe, in the inert
dictatorship of the provisional government, and in the insignificant presidency
of General Cavignac and Louis Bonaparte.
We prove our thesis, in the second place, by explaining how,
through the economic reform, through industrial solidarity and the organization
of universal suffrage, the people passes from spontaneity to reflection and
consciousness; act, no longer from impulse and enthusiasm, but with design;
maintains itself without masters and servants, without delegates as without
aristocrats, absolutely as would an individual. Thus, the conception of person,
the idea of the me, becomes extended and generalized; as there is an individual
person or me, so there is a collective person or me; in the one case as in the
other will, actions, soul, spirit, life, unknown in their principle,
inconceivable in their essence, result from the animating and vital fact of
organization. The psychology of nations and of humanity, like the psychology of
man, becomes a possible science. It was this demonstration that we referred to
in our publications on circulation and credit as well as in the fourteenth
chapter of the manifesto of “La Voix du Peuple” relative to the constitution.
So, when Louis Blanc and Pierre Leroux assume the position
of defenders of the State,—that is, of the external constitution of the public
power,—they only reproduce, in a varied form peculiar to themselves which they
have not yet made known, that old fiction of representative government, whose
integral formula, whose completest expression, is still the constitutional
monarchy. Did we, then, accomplish the Revolution of February in order to
attain this retrogressive contradiction?
It seems to us—what do you say, readers?—that the question
begins to exhibit itself in a somewhat clearer light; that the weak-minded,
after what we have just said, will be able to form an idea of the State; that
they will understand how republicans can inquire if it is indispensable, after
an economic revolution which changes all social relations, to maintain, to
please the vanity of pretended statesmen, and at a cost of two thousand
millions per annum, this parasitic organ called government. And the honorable
delegates of the Luxembourg, who, being seated in the arm-chairs of the
peerage, therefore think themselves politicians, and claim so courageously an
exclusive understanding of the Revolution, doubtless will fear no longer that
we, in our capacity of the most intelligent and the strongest, after having
abolished government, as useless and too costly, may establish the tyranny of
chaos. We deny the State and the government; we affirm in the same breath the
autonomy of the people and its majority. How can we be upholders of tyranny,
aspirants for the ministry, competitors of Louis Blanc and Pierre Leroux?
In truth, we do not understand the logic of our adversaries.
They accept a principle without troubling themselves about its consequences;
they approve, for example, the equality of taxation which the tax on capital
realizes; they adopt popular, mutual, and gratuitous credit, for all these
terms are synonymous; they cheer at the dethronement of capital and the
emancipation of labor; then, when it remains to draw the anti-governmental
conclusions from these premises, they protest, they continue to talk of
politics and government, without inquiring whether government is compatible
with industrial liberty and equality; whether there is a possibility of a
political science, when there is a necessity for an economic science! Property
they attack without scruple, in spite of its venerable antiquity; but they bow
before power like church-wardens before the holy sacrament. Government is to
them the necessary and immutable a priori, the principle of principles, the
eternal archeus.
Certainly, we do not offer our affirmations as proofs; we
know, as well as any one, on what conditions a proposition is demonstrated. We
only say that, before proceeding to a new constitution of the State, we must
inquire whether, in view of the economic reforms which the Revolution imposes
upon us, the State itself should not be abolished; whether this end of
political institutions does not result from the meaning and bearing of economic
reform. We ask whether, in fact, after the explosion of February, after the
establishment of universal suffrage, the declaration of the omnipotence of the
masses, and the henceforth inevitable subordination of power to the popular
will, any government whatever is still possible, whether a government would not
be placed perpetually in the alternative either of submissively following the
blind and contradictory injunctions of the multitude, or of intentionally
deceiving it, as the provisional government has done, as demagogues in all ages
have done. We ask, at least, which of the various attributes of the State
should be retained and strengthened, which abolished. For, should we find, as
may still be expected, that, of all the present attributes of the State, not
one can survive the economic reform, it would be quite necessary to admit, on
the strength of this negative demonstration that, in the new condition of
society, the State is nothing., can be nothing; in short, that the only way to
organize democratic government is to abolish government,
Instead of this positive, practical, realistic analysis of
the revolutionary movement, what course do our pretended apostles take? They go
to consult Lycurgus, Plato, Orpheus, and all the mythological oracles; they
interrogate the ancient legends; they appeal to remotest antiquity for the
solution of problems exclusively modern, and then give us for answer the
whimsical illuminations of their brain.
Once more: is this the science of society and of the
Revolution which must, at first sight, solve all problems; a science
essentially practical and immediately applicable; a science eminently
traditional doubtless, but above all thoroughly progressive, in which progress
takes place through the systematic negation of tradition itself?
II. Of the end or object of the State.
We have just seen that the idea of the State, considered in
its nature, rests entirely on an hypothesis which is at least doubtful,—that of
the impersonality and the physical, intellectual, and moral inertia of the
masses. We shall now prove that this same idea of the State, considered in its
object, rests on another hypothesis, still more improbable than the first,—that
of the permanence of antagonism in humanity, an hypothesis which is itself a consequence
of the primitive dogma of the fall or of original sin.
We continue to quote “Le Nouveau Monde:”
“What would happen,” asks Louis Blanc, “if we should leave
the most intelligent or the strongest to place obstacles in the way of the
development of the faculties of one who is less strong or less intelligent?
Liberty would be destroyed.
“How prevent this crime? By interposing between oppressor
and oppressed the whole power of the people.
“If James oppresses Peter, shall the thirty-four millions of
men of whom French society is composed run all at once to protect Peter, to
maintain liberty? To pretend such a thing would be buffoonery.
“How then shall society intervene?
“Through those whom it has chosen to REPRESENT it for this
purpose.
“But these REPRESENTATIVES of society, these servants of the
people, who are they? The State.
“Then the State is only society itself, acting as society,
to prevent—what?—oppression; to maintain—what?—liberty.”
That is clear. The State is a REPRESENTATION of society,
externally organized to protect the weak against the strong; in other words, to
preserve peace between disputants and maintain order. Louis Blanc has not gone,
far, as we see, to find the object of the State. It can be traced from Grotius,
Justinian, Cicero, etc., in all the authors who ever have written on public
right. It is the Orphic tradition related by Horace:—
Sylvestres homines sacer interpresque deorum.
Cædíbus et victu fœdo deterruit Orpheus,
Dictus ob hoc lenire tigres rabidosque leones,
Dictus et Amphion, Thebanæ conditor arcis,
Saxa movere sono testudinis, et prece blanda
Ducere quo vellet....
“The divine Orpheus, the interpreter of the gods, called men
from the depths of the forests and filled them with a horror of murder and of
human flesh. Consequently it was said of him that he tamed lions and tigers, as
later it was said of Amphion, founder of Thebes, that he moved the stones by
the sound of his lyre, and led them whither he wished by the charm of his
prayer.”
Socialism, we know, does not require with certain people
great efforts of the imagination. They imitate, flatly enough, the old
mythologies; they copy Catholicism, while declaiming against it; they ape
power, which they lust after; then they shout with all their strength: Liberty,
Equality, Fraternity; and the circle is complete. One passes for a revelator, a
reformer, a democratic and social restorer, one is named as a candidate for the
ministry of progress,—nay, even for the dictatorship of the Republic!
So, by the confession of Louis Blanc, power is born of
barbarism; its organization bears witness to a state of ferocity and violence
among primitive men,—an effect of the utter absence of commerce and industry.
To this savagism the State had to put an end by opposing to the force of each
individual a superior force capable, in the absence of any other argument, of
restraining his will. The constitution of the State supposes, then, as we have
just said, a profound social antagonism, homo homini lupus. Louis Blanc himself
says this when, after having divided men into the strong and the weak,
disputing with each other like wild beasts for their food, he interposes
between them, as a mediator, the State.
Then the State would be useless; the State would lack an
object as well as a motive; the State would have to take itself away,—if there
should come a day when, from any cause whatever, society should contain neither
strong nor weak,— that is, when the inequality of physical and intellectual
powers could not be a cause of robbery and oppression, independently of the
protection, more fictitious than real by the way, of the State.
Now, this is precisely the thesis that we maintain today.
The power that tempers morals, that gradually substitutes
the rule of right for the rule of force, that establishes security, that
creates step by step liberty and equality, is, in a much higher degree than
religion and the State, labor; first, the labor of commerce and industry; next,
science, which spiritualizes it; in the last analysis, art, its immortal
flower. Religion by its promises and its threats, the State by its tribunals
and its armies, gave to the sentiment of justice, which was too weak among
primitive men, the only sanction intelligible to savage minds. For us, whom
industry, science, literature, art, have corrupted, as Jean Jacques said, this
sanction lies elsewhere; we find it in the division of property, in the
machinery of industry, in the growth of luxury, in the overruling desire for
well-being,—a desire which imposes upon all a necessity of labor. After the
barbarism of the early ages, after the price of caste and the feudal
constitution of primitive society, a last element of slavery still
remained,—capital. Capital having lost its way, the laborer—that is, the
merchant, the mechanic, the farmer, the savant, the artist—no longer needs
protection; his protection is his talent, his knowledge is his industry. After
the dethronement of capital, the continuance of the State, far from protecting
liberty, can only compromise liberty.
He has a sorry idea of the human race—of its essence, its
perfectibility, its destiny—who conceive it as an agglomeration of individuals
necessarily exposed, by the inequality of physical and intellectual forces, to
the constant danger of reciprocal spoliation or the tyranny of a few. Such an
idea is a proof of the most retrogressive philosophy; it belongs to those days
of barbarism when the absence of the true elements of social order left to the
genius of the legislator no method of action save that of force; when the
supremacy of a pacifying and avenging power appeared to all as the just
consequence of a previous degradation and an original stain. To give our whole
thought, we regard political and judicial institutions as the exoteric and
concrete formula of the myth of the fall, the mystery of redemption, and the
sacrament of penitence. It is curious to see pretended socialists, enemies or
rivals of Church and State, copying all that they blaspheme,—the representative
system in politics, the dogma of the fall in religion.
Since they talk so much of doctrine, we frankly declare that
such is not ours.
In our view, the moral condition of society is modified and
ameliorated at the same rate as its economic condition. The morality of a wild,
ignorant, and idle people is one thing; that of an industrious and artistic
people another: consequently, the social guarantees that prevail among the
former are quite different from those that prevail among the latter. In a
society transformed, almost unconsciously, by its economic development, there
is no longer either strong or weak; there are only laborers whose faculties and
means incessantly tend, through industrial solidarity and the guarantee of
circulation, to become equalized. In vain, to assure the right and the duty of
each, does the imagination go back to that idea of authority and government
which attests the profound despair of souls long terrified by the police and
the priesthood: the simplest examination of the attributes of the State
suffices to demonstrate that, if inequality of fortunes, oppression, robbery,
and misery are not our eternal inheritance, the first leprosy to be eradicated,
after capitalistic exploitation, the first plague to be wiped out, is the
State.
See, in fact, budget in hand, what the State is.
The State is the army. Reformer, do you need an army to
defend you? If so, your idea of public security is Cæsar’s and Napoleon’s. You
are not a republican; you are a despot.
The State is the police; city police, rural police, police
of the waters and forests. Reformer, do you need police? Then your idea of
order is Fouché’s, Gisquet’s, Carussidière’s, and M. Carlier’s. You are not a
democrat, you are a spy.
The State is the whole judicial system; justices of the
peace, tribunals of first instance, courts of appeal, court of cassation, high
court, tribunals of experts, commercial tribunals, council of prefects, State
council, councils of war. Reformer, do you need all this judiciary? Then your
idea of justice is M. Baroche’s, M. Dupin’s, and Perrin Dandin’s. You are not a
socialist; you are a red-tapist.
The State is the treasury, the budget. Reformer, you do not
desire the abolition of taxation? Then your idea of public wealth is M. Thiers’s
who thinks that the largest budgets are the best. You are not an organizer of
labor; you are an exciseman.
The State is the custom-house. Reformer, do you need, for
the protection of national labor, differential duties and toll-houses? Then
your idea of commerce and circulation is M. Fould’s and M. Rothschild’s. You
are not an apostle of fraternity; you are a Jew.
The State is the public debt, the mint, the sinking fund,
the savings-banks, etc. Reformer, are these the foundation of your science?
Then your idea of social economy is that of MM. Humann, Lacave-Laplagne,
Garnier-Pagès, Passy, Duclerc, and the “Man with Forty Crowns.” You are a
Turcaret.
The State—but we must stop. There is nothing, absolutely
nothing, in the State , from the top of the hierarchy to its foot, which is not
an abuse to be reformed, a parasite to be exterminated, an instrument of
tyranny to be destroyed. And you talk to us of maintaining the State, of
extending the functions or the State, of increasing the power of the State! Go
to, you are not a revolutionist; for the true revolutionist is essentially a
simplifier and a liberal. You are a mystifier, a juggler; you are a marplot.
III. Of an ulterior destiny of the State.
There arises in favor of the State a last hypothesis. The
fact that the State, say the pseudo-democrats, hitherto has performed only a
rôle of parasitism and tyranny is no reason for denying it a nobler and more
humane destiny. The State is destined to become the principal organ of
production, consumption, and circulation; the initiator of liberty and
equality.
For liberty and equality are the State.
Credit is the State.
Commerce, agriculture, and manufactures are the State.
Canals, railroads, mines, insurance companies, as well as
tobacco-shops and post-offices, are the State.
Public education is the State.
The State, in fine, dropping its negative attributes to
clothe itself with positive ones, must change from the oppressor, parasite, and
conservative it ever has been into an organizer, producer, and servant. That
would be feudalism regenerated, the hierarchy of industrial associations,
organized and graded according to a potent formula the secret of which Pierre
Leroux still hides from our sight.
Thus, the organizers of the State suppose—for in all this
they only go from supposition to supposition—that the State can change its
nature, turn itself around, so to speak; from Satan become an archangel; and,
after having lived for centuries by blood and slaughter like a wild beast, feed
upon plants with the deer, and give suck to the lambs. Such is the teaching of
Louis Blanc and Pierre Leroux; such, as we said long ago, is the whole secret
of socialism.
“We love the tutelary, generous, devoted government, taking
as its motto those profound words of the gospel, ‘Whosoever of you will be the
chiefest, shall be the servant of all;’ and we hate the deprived, corrupting,
oppressive government, making the people its prey. We admire it representing
the generous and living portion of humanity; we abhor it when it represents the
cadaverous portion. We revolt against the insolence, usurpation, and robbery
involved in the idea of the MASTER-STATE; and we applaud that which is
touching, fruitful, and noble in the idea of the SERVANT-STATE. Or better:
there is a belief which we hold a thousand times dearer than life,—our belief
in the approaching and final TRANSFORMATION of power.
That is the triumphant passage from the old world to the new. All the government. of Europe rest today on the idea of the MASTER-STATE; but they are dancing desperately the dance of the dead.”—“Le Nouveau Monde,” November 16, 1849.
That is the triumphant passage from the old world to the new. All the government. of Europe rest today on the idea of the MASTER-STATE; but they are dancing desperately the dance of the dead.”—“Le Nouveau Monde,” November 16, 1849.
Pierre Leroux is a thorough believer in these ideas. What he
wishes, what he teaches, and what he calls for is a regeneration of the
State,—he has not told us yet whereby and by whom this regeneration should be
effected,—just as he wishes and calls for a regeneration of Christianity
without, as yet, having stated his dogma and given his credo.
We believe, in opposition to Pierre Leroux and Louis Blanc,
that the theory of the tutelary, generous, devoted, productive, initiative,
organizing, liberal and progressive State is a utopia, a pure illusion of their
intellectual vision. Pierre Leroux and Louis Blanc seem to us like a man who,
standing above a mirror and seeing his image reversed, should pretend that this
image must become a reality some day and replace (pardon us the expression) his
natural person.
This is what separates us from these two men, whose talents
and services, whatever they may say, we have never dreamed of denying, but
whose stubborn hallucination we deplore. We do not believe in the
SERVANT-STATE: to us it is a flat contradiction.
Servant and master, when applied to the State, are
synonymous terms; just as more and less, when applied to equality, are
identical terms. The proprietor, by interest on capital, demands more than
equality; communism, by the formula, to each according to his needs, allows
less than equality: always inequality; and that is why we are neither a
communist nor a proprietor. Likewise, whoever says master-State says usurpation
of the public power; whoever says servant-State says delegation of the public
power: always an alienation of this power, always a power, always an external,
arbitrary authority instead of the immanent, inalienable, untransferable
authority of citizens; always more or less than liberty. It is for this reason
that we are opposed to the State.
Further, to leave metaphysics and return to the field of
experience, here is what we have to say to Louis Blanc and Pierre Leroux.
You pretend and affirm that the State, that the government,
can, and ought to be, wholly changed in its principle, in its essence, in its
action, in its relations with citizens, as well as in its results that thus the
State, a bankrupt and a counterfeiter, should be the sole source of credit;
that for so many centuries an enemy of knowledge, and at the present moment
still hostile to primary instruction and the liberty of the press, it is its
business to officially provide for the instruction of citizens; that, after
having left commerce, industry, agriculture, and all the machinery of wealth to
develop themselves without its aid, often even in spite of its resistance, it
belongs to it to take the initiative in the whole field of labor as in the
world of ideas, that, in fine, the eternal enemy of liberty, it yet ought, not
to leave liberty to itself, but to create and direct liberty. It is this
marvelous transformation of the State that constitutes, in your opinion, the
present Revolution.
There lies upon you, then, the twofold obligation: first, of
establishing the truth of your hypothesis by showing its traditional
legitimacy, exhibiting its historical titles, and developing its philosophy; in
the second place, of applying it in practice.
Now, it appears already that both theory and practice, in
your hypothesis, formally contradict the idea itself, and the facts of the
past, and the most authentic tendencies of humanity.
Your theory, we say, involves a contradiction in its terms,
since it pretends to make liberty a creation of the State, while the State, on
the contrary, is to be a creation of liberty. In fact, if the State imposes
itself upon my will, the State is master; I am not free; the theory is
undermined.
It contradicts the facts of the past, since it is certain,
as you yourselves admit, that everything that has been produced within the
sphere of human activity of a positive, good, and beautiful character, was the
product of liberty exclusively, acting independently of the State, and almost
always in opposition to the State; which leads directly to this proposition,
which ruins your system, that liberty is sufficient unto itself and does not
need the State.
Finally, your theory contradicts the manifest tendencies of
civilization; since, instead of continually adding to individual liberty and
dignity by making every human soul, according to Kant’s precept, a pattern of
entire humanity, one face of the collective soul, you subordinate the private
person to the public person; you submit the individual to the group; you absorb
the citizen in the State.
It is for you to remove all these contradictions by a
principle superior to liberty and to the State. We, who simply deny the State;
who, resolutely, following the line of liberty, remain faithful to the
revolutionary practice,—it is not for us to demonstrate to you the falsity of
your hypothesis; we await your proofs. The master-State is lost; you are with
us in admitting it. As for the servant-State, we do not know what it may be; we
distrust it as supreme hypocrisy. The servant-State seems to us quite the same
thing as a servant-mistress; we do not wish it; with our present light, we
prefer to espouse Liberty in legitimate marriage. Explain, then, if you can,
why, after having demolished the State through love of this adored liberty, we
must now, in consequence of the same love, return to the State. Until you have
solved this problem, we shall continue to protest against all government, all authority,
all power; we shall maintain, through all and against all, the prerogative of
liberty. We shall say to you: Liberty is, for us, a thing gained; now, you know
the rule of law: Melior est conditio possidentis. Produce your titles to the
reorganization of government; otherwise, no government!
To sum up:
The State is the external constitution of the social power.
The constitution supposes, in principle, that society is a
creature of the mind, destitute of spontaneity, providence, unity, needing for
its action to be fictitiously represented by one or more elected or hereditary
commissioners: an hypothesis the falsity of which the economic development of
society and the organization of universal suffrage agree in demonstrating.
The constitution of the State supposes further, as to its
object, that antagonism or a state of war is the essential and irrevocable
condition of humanity, a condition which necessitates, between the weak and the
strong, the intervention of a coercive power to put an end to their struggles
by universal oppression We maintain that, in this respect, the mission of the
State is ended; that, by the division of labor, industrial solidarity, the
desire for well-being, and the equal distribution of capital and taxation,
liberty and justice obtain surer guarantees than any that ever were afforded
them by religion and the State.
As for utilitarian transformation of the State, we consider
it as a utopia contradicted at once by governmental tradition, and the
revolutionary tendency, and the spirit of the henceforth admitted economic
reforms. In any case, we say that to liberty alone it would belong to
reorganize power, which is equivalent at present to the complete exclusion of
power.
As a result, either no social revolution, or no more government;
such is our solution of the political problem.
William B. Greene translation
THE STATE
Translated by William B. Greene
Louis Blanc asks himself, What Is the State?
And he answers himself thus:
“The State, under monarchical rule, is the power of one
person only, the tyranny of a single man.
“The State, under oligarchical rule, is the power of a few
men, the tyranny of certain ones.
“The State, under aristocratic rule, is the power of a
class, the tyranny of several persons.
“The State, under anarchical rule is the power of the first
comer who happens to be the stronger and more intelligent; it is tyranny in
chaos.
“The State, under democratic rule, is the power of the whole
people, served by elect delegates: it is the reign of liberty.”
Among Louis Blanc’s twenty-five thousand, or thirty
thousand, readers, perhaps there are not ten to whom this definition does not
appear to be rigorously demonstrative, and who do not repeat, after the
master:—the State is the power of one, of several, of many, of all or of the
first comer, according to the qualification of the word State by the adjectives
monarchial, oligarchical, aristocratic, democratic, or anarchical.
Louis Blanc’s readers were never, we presume, taught Greek.
Otherwise they would know that their friend and leader, Louis Blanc, simply
translates the Greek words monos, one; aligoi, certain ones; aristoï, the upper
crust; demos, the people; and a, which simply means no. Now mark the artifice! Louis
Blanc finds it sufficient, in his translation to employ the word tyranny four
times, tyranny of a single person, tyranny of several, etc. and to suppress it
once, power of the people served by its elect delegates, to obtain universal
applause. Every State that is not democratic is according to Louis Blanc,
tyranny. But anarchy is singled out to be treated with special severity; it is
the power of the first-comer who happens to be the stronger and more
intelligent: it is tyranny in chaos. What an intolerable beast that first-comer
must be, who first-comer as he is finds himself to be the strongest and most
intelligent, and who exercises his tyranny in chaos! Who, after this, will
prefer anarchy to the amiable government of the people, served so well (as we
know by painful experience) by its elected delegates? This is triumphant! Here
we are, all of us, knocked flat at the first lick! * * * What is the State? The
question must be answered.
The State is the EXTERIOR constitution of the social power.
By this external constitution of its power and sovereignty, the people never
governs itself. Sometimes an individual, sometimes several individuals, either
by elective or by hereditary title, govern the people, and with such
responsibility to the people as we are perfectly aware from our experience. The
Greeks called this exterior constitution of the people arche, principality,
authority, government. The existence of this arche is logically grounded on the
hypothesis that the people—the collective entity that is called society—can
neither govern itself, or thing, act, or express itself, from its own
spontaneity; that is requires, in order that it may do either of these things,
to be represented by one or more individuals, clothed with elective or
hereditary authority, who may act as depositories of the power of the people,
or as its agents. According to this theory, the collective society is an
abstract entity only, without power to manifest itself directly, and which
must, in order to render itself efficacious, incarnate itself in a monarchy, in
an aristocratic usurpation, or in a democratic mandate.
Now, it is precisely this notion of a collective entity, of
its life, of its activity, of its unity, of its individuality, of its
personality,—do you hear that,—which cause us to repudiate the State, to
repudiate the government, to repudiate all incarnation of the popular power,
outside the mass, whether hereditary royalties, feudal institutions, or
democratic delegations.
We affirm, on the contrary, that the people, that society,
that the mass, can and ought to govern itself, and to think, act, rise up, and
stand, like a single man, without the instrumentality of any of those
appliances which formerly were despotic, which now are aristocratic, and which,
from time to time, have been pretended delegates, or representatives, tools or
servants of the Crown. These last we simply characterize as agitators of the
people, or demagogues,
In two words:
We repudiate both the government and the State, because we
affirm (what no Statesman ever yet believed or affirmed) the spontaneity and
self-action of the masses.
We go therefore, for anarchy, which expresses, as it is
evident from what has already been said, the highest limit of liberty and order
to which humanity can attain. ANARCHY the government of the people by itself,
without the intervention of kings, aristocrats, or demagogues; self-government
is the true formula of the Republic.—Voix du Peuple, Dec. 3 1849
------------------------------
For More Articles On The Problem Of Stating Please See The Page 'The Problem Of Statism - A Collection Of Articles.'
------------------------------
For More Articles On The Problem Of Stating Please See The Page 'The Problem Of Statism - A Collection Of Articles.'